The Epistemic Significance of #MeToo
Karyn L. Freedman
About “The Epistemic Significance of #MeToo”
Karyn L. Freedman is a professor of philosophy at the University of Guelph. Her research focuses on feminist philosophy, epistemology, and the philosophy of trauma. In her 2020 paper, “The Epistemic Significance of #MeToo,” published in the Feminist Philosophy Quarterly, Freedman examines how the #MeToo movement has influenced knowledge production and understanding regarding sexual violence and harassment. She argues that the collective sharing of personal testimonies within the #MeToo movement enhances epistemic value in several ways:
- For Survivors as Hearers: When survivors encounter stories similar to their own, it aids in contextualizing and understanding their personal experiences, leading to an enhanced self-awareness and validation.
- For Society at Large: The proliferation of #MeToo testimonies challenges and seeks to replace false, dominant narratives about sexual violence with authentic accounts, thereby fostering a more accurate societal understanding of these issues.
- For Survivors as Tellers: When a survivor’s testimony is believed, it not only affirms their credibility but also contributes to their personal epistemic agency and healing process.
Freedman also addresses the significant personal costs that individuals may endure when sharing their #MeToo testimonies. She emphasizes that these costs are often underestimated, leading to a distorted perception of the teller’s credibility and rationality. By highlighting these challenges, Freedman advocates for a greater acknowledgment of the bravery involved in sharing such testimonies and calls for increased support and belief in survivors’ accounts.
Before You Read
Before engaging with “The Epistemic Significance of #MeToo,” consider the broader context of the #MeToo movement, which began as a grassroots effort to shed light on the prevalence of sexual harassment and assault. Reflect on how personal narratives can influence public discourse and policy changes. Think about the role of social media in amplifying marginalized voices and how collective storytelling can serve as a powerful tool for social change. Additionally, be mindful of the emotional weight that such testimonies carry and the potential retraumatization that can occur for both the teller and the audience. This awareness will help in appreciating the depth and significance of the epistemic contributions discussed in Freedman’s work.
Guiding Questions
- How does the sharing of personal testimonies within the #MeToo movement contribute to the collective understanding of sexual violence?
- What are the potential personal costs for individuals who share their #MeToo stories, and how might society better support them?
- In what ways can the #MeToo movement challenge and change dominant societal narratives about sexual harassment and assault?
- How does believing survivors’ testimonies impact their personal epistemic agency and the broader societal perception of sexual violence?
The Epistemic Significance of #MeToo
Abstract
Introduction [1]
There are important social, political, moral, and economic consequences of #MeToo, but in what follows, I look at its epistemic significance, for if this hashtag activism has shown us anything it is that personal stories make tangible unpleasant truths in a way that theorizing can miss. In part I of this paper, I argue that #MeTootestimonyincreasesepistemic value, a term I use to refer to standard forms of cognitive success, including an increase in truth, knowledge, or understanding.[4]
Part 1:Representation, Marginalization,and #MeToo
Certain aspects of marginalized social identities are ours from birth, and others come to us later in life, sometimes by choice and at other times unbidden, but in all cases, marginalized identities receive representational short shrift. They are largely absent from our scholarly canons and history books and have been relegated to the fringes of mainstream media and popular culture, at least until recently.[5]That is hardly surprising, since part of what it means to be marginalized is to lack the power and influence to tell one’s own story, to be denied a voice and a platform to use it, and to risk serious threats to one’s health, safety, livelihood, and community when one does.[6]
When it comes to testimony about sexual violence and sexual harassment, there are also very real, if less tangible, costs to one’s sense of self, since when marginalized individuals do go public with these sorts of stories, against all obstacles, they are often not properly heard. Their testimony is routinely filtered through distorting prejudice and dismissed as lacking credibility, epitomizing the central case of what Miranda Fricker (2007) has called testimonial injustice; these individuals are wronged in their capacities as knowers in virtue of a prejudice against them, qua social type(Fricker 2007, 45). The deflated credibility they receive as tellers results in an intrinsic epistemic injustice, insofar as they are degraded in their very humanity, qua knowers.[7] The routine diminishment faced by marginalized tellers is part and parcel of the humiliation of patriarchy; of being a woman, of being not white, of being queer, trans, or disabled. But remarkably, since October2017, while simultaneously suffering various social and political harms as a result of a US administration led by a dangerous president, who himself has been accused of sexual misconduct by no fewer than 22 women,[8] we have seen an increase in stories about sexual harassment and sexual violence. This started with the toppling of one of America’s most powerful men, the Hollywood movie mogul Harvey Weinstein, following a New York Times story by Jodi Kantor and Megan Twohey that detailed Weinstein’s decades of predatory sexual behavior;[9] and so began the international movement known as #MeToo.[10]With over 19 million tweets in the first year alone,[11]we have since seen the downfall of one after another of some of America’s most powerful men, including Louis C.K., Bill O’Reilly, Kevin Spacey, Al Franken, Charlie Rose, Matt Lauer—men who, as Soraya Chemaly points out, “had for decades chosen, framed, investigated, written about, and produced our culture’s stories about politics, gender, and violence”(Chemaly 2018, 141–142).That some of the very men who had been controlling national narratives about gender-based violence were simultaneously guilty of perpetuating the problem induced a serious reckoning.[12] “The anger window was open,” as Rebecca Traister put it, referring to the collective mood following Weinstein’s downfall, and in the short time since then we have witnessed a global surge of rage, what Traister has aptly described as a“‘70s-style, organic, mass radical rage, exploding in unpredictable directions” (2018, 141, 143).[13]
1.1 The Isolation of Survivors (Uptick #1)
I know from personal experience how important it can be for survivors of sexual violence and sexual harassment to have the opportunity to hear other people’s stories and to see similar kinds of traumatic experiences represented by others. This can help us make sense of our own experience by contextualizing it thereby reframing these phenomena not as personal problems—something that happened to me, for instance, because of what I was wearing, who I was with, or how much I had to drink—but rather as widespread sociological phenomena. Not only can this help survivors combat the corrosive shame that is part of the aftermath of sexual violence and harassment, but more to the point here, it can help us better understand what we have been through by viewing it through a broad social and political frame of reference. In order to illustrate the epistemic value survivors gain by hearing #MeToo stories, I will start by telling one of my own. This is a story about something that happened to me when I was a graduate student in philosophy, over twenty years ago. It is an experience that is a bit hard for me to remember, not because my memory is failing me, but because it is painful to recall. This is not a story about sexual harassment in the discipline of philosophy(although I have my fair share of those stories as well).[14]Rather,itisa story about how I was doing, back in 1996,having just moved away from home to do my PhD in philosophy. This was a difficult time in my life, and not just because of the various pressures one faces when moving to a new city and entering a new university and new program, although none of that was easy. But I had other problems. Six years earlier, when I was twenty-two years old I was raped. I had been travelling at the time, having just arrived in Paris to meet an ex-boyfriend. We had been invited to stay as houseguests at the apartment of his friend and mentor, along with another house guest, a thirty-year-old Frenchman, whom I had met for the first time just that day. He seemed friendly enough, and a few hours later, when I was alone with him in the apartment, he kindly made me dinner, and then afterward, pressing a long sharp knife against my neck, proceeded to rape me.[15] It was a violent sexual assault, and I was lucky to have come out of it alive, but the experience left me destabilized. In the aftermath, I found myself reeling, awash with shame, so much so that I could not bear to have others know what had happened to me. And so, like many women in similar kinds of situations, I decided to keep it a secret, telling no one outside of my family and two closest friends. I buried the trauma of the experience deep within, hoping that would make it disappear, but unfortunately the body does not process trauma that way, or at least, not properly.[16]Instead, it weighed me down like an anchor. I struggled with crushing anxiety, cycling through recurring panic attacks, sleep deprivation, and troubled relationships with men—each a classic symptom of PTSD, although I did not know that at the time.[17]One of the few places I was able to find relief from my wearing inner life was as a student in the world of thinking that philosophy offers. When immersed in my studies, I could almost ignore the debilitating consequences of being raped. Over the years, I became adept at covering up any perceptible signs of distress, but by the time I started my PhD, the energy required to sustain this double life was almost too much for me, and my anxiety worsened.
It was in this context that I enrolled in my first year of classes, in order to fulfill the coursework component of my degree. One of the classes on offer was being taught by a distinguished professor. It was a popular class, drawing students from various cohorts, and I signed up for it. I will never forget the first day of that class. There must have been 20–25 students crammed into a room that was meant to hold fewer than that. It was set up with long tables around the perimeter, forming a rectangle. When I arrived, the professor was sitting at the front of the room, which by then was already half full. I had to make my way around the crowded outer edges in order to find an empty seat in the back corner, about as far away from the doorway as you could get, which was the start of my problems that day. As soon as I sat down, I was in trouble. I immediately felt trapped, just as I had been, six years earlier, in that apartment in Paris. Once again, I had failed to anticipate what was coming next, and the triggering feelings heaved through me. As the remaining students filed in, I became unable to catch a deep breath. My heart was pounding as I found myself in the familiar grip of a panic attack. I remember squeezing my hands together under the table, hoping that I wouldn’t faint, hoping that this one would pass quickly, but then the professor began to talk. He announced that we would be starting class by going around the room and introducing ourselves. At that, the feeling of being trapped intensified, and the room unspooled before me. I did not pass out, but when the introductions finally reached me, I was not able to speak. I choked out my name, my quivering voice betraying the panic within, bringing every surprised eye in the room to rest on me.
Solidarity Stories and Representation
When I think about that experience now, what is most striking to me is not how mortified I had been, or how everyone in the room looked at me with a mix of pity and horror, but how truly alone I felt at the time. I was not unaware of the existence of other rape survivors, but personally, I did not know a single one. It is hard to overstate how important it would have been for me, back then, to have had easy access to a multitude of stories by other survivors, by other women who had had experiences like mine; to have been able to feel that kind of solidarity, and to have been able to see my experience represented at a time when I was too vulnerable to make myself visible in the same way. That would have been integral in helping me understand this dramatic and uninvited change to my life, to my very identity; it would have saved me years of confusion, isolation, and shame.
When I further reflect about that in the context of my relative privilege at the time—specifically, of being a doctoral student at a reputable university, of being cis, white, heterosexual, able bodied, and middle class, and thus checking off all the boxes which guaranteed that at least I did not look out of place(however shattered I was feeling)—I cannot help but think about the legions of women, and men too, with far fewer entitlements, who have experienced sexual harassment and sexual assault and who, for one reason or another, had been isolated and suffering in silence until #MeToo.The injustice of it all is highlighted when we consider the routine silencing and lack of visibility of people on the margins. As we have seen over the past few years, representation—even in 280 characters or less—can be life-altering, and particularly so for members of groups who have been systematically disadvantaged. Although a hashtag will not heal you, seeing yourself in someone else’s story can be deeply impactful.[18]Not only can it help us make sense of our own experience by framing it in a broader social and political context, but having the chance to see someone come out the other side can be profound; it can set you on a path that you had never before imagined possible.[19]
1.2 Motivated IgnoranceandEpistemic Friction(Uptick #2)
The epistemic value survivors gain by seeing their realities represented is one significant consequence of#MeToo stories, but that value extends beyond individual survivors. Storytellers have a singular power to effect broad social and cultural change through their testimony, which can make unpleasant truths about sexual assault and sexual harassment tangible in a way that theorizing can miss. Not everyone has an equal opportunity to make her voice heard, but those who do open up a space in the social imaginary and thereby provide uniquely persuasive kind of evidence in support of nonnormative identities. Stories thus provide epistemic friction, to borrow a phrase from José Medina(2013).They offer alternative representations that mitigate against the widespread resistance among dominantly situated knowers to acknowledge, in this case, the realities of sexual violence and sexual harassment against women. I call this resistance “male ignorance, “for it is a phenomenon that bears a distinct resemblance to what Charles Mills calls “white ignorance, “which is a motivated ignorance that maintains the status quo and allows for privileged groups to perpetuate dominant but false narratives about black people, thus enabling, as Mills (2007, 13) puts it, “a self-representation in which differential white privilege, and the need to correct for it, does not exist.”Likewise, in the case of male ignorance, the refusal to recognize and accept the truth about sexual violence and sexual harassment against women—and this includes all women: cis, trans, genderqueer, and gender nonconforming—whether brazen and willful or lazy and indifferent, provides concrete benefits for men. In cases of male ignorance and white ignorance there is an absence of knowledge, or better yet, an absence of true belief, which is not epistemically neutral but is instead motivated, and thus represents a cognitive failure, as I discuss below.
Just as white ignorance is perpetuated by racist individuals and also deeply embedded in our institutions and norms, such that biases are enacted even by those who aren’t straightforwardly racist (Mills 2007, 21), so too male ignorance is individualistic and structural, blatant and implicit. And in the same way that white ignorance results in concrete material, social, and institutional benefits for white people in the form of jobs, wealth, opportunities, housing, upward mobility, freedom of movement, freedom from incarceration, and freedom from the expectation of incarceration,[20] there are likewise material, social, and institutional benefits for men—and, it is worth emphasizing, in particular white, cis, straight men—that result from male ignorance. These men have the advantage of being viewed as inherently credible; they have the criminal justice system, with the presumption of innocence on their side; they have the freedom to remain unaware of the short-and long-term impact of trauma; and they have the benefit of receiving sympathy—or better yet, him pathy[21]—when they are accused, even convicted, of serious and criminal wrongdoing, as we have seen repeatedly in high-profile cases over the years.[22]
Motivated Ignorance: The New View
As Mills argues, incases of motivated ignorance, these benefits provide an incentivized reason for people in positions of relative privilege to ignore facts that illuminate that privilege(2007, 31), and the same can be said when it comes to male ignorance. In both cases, the facts in question can be easily known. They do not make up the dominant narratives, but neither are they hidden, hard to find, or obscure. Indeed, people have to work at remaining ignorant of patent social realities about racial injustice and sexual violence and sexual harassment against women, and their relative privilege gives them a reason to do so, which is what makes these cases of ignorance motivated.[23]
Ignorance is often referred to as a kind of non knowing, which it is, but the distinguishing feature of motivated ignorance is a lack of true beliefs, as opposed to, say, true beliefs that fall short of knowledge because they lack justification, or sufficient justification.[24]As such, motivated cases line up with what Rik Peels calls the New View of ignorance.[25]On this account, we can say that a subject is ignorant that p in three kinds of cases:
- Disbelieving Ignorance: S considers that p but rejects p as false, even though p is true;
- Suspending Ignorance: S considers that p but suspends judgment about p, even though p is true; or
- Deep Ignorance: S does not even consider that p, in the first place, and hence neither believes, suspends judgment, nor disbelieves that p, even though p is true(Le Morvan and Peels 2016, 26).
Male Ignorance: Not Having to Know
A thorough analysis of epistemic culpability in cases of motivated ignorance goes beyond my purposes in this paper.[26]However, I will note here that epistemic culpability is relatively easy to assess in the first two kinds of cases, wherein the subject considers the facts of the matter, but fails to believe truly. Arguably, in these cases, the subject’s failure to properly assess evidence can be pinned to bad epistemic practices that are cultivated to maintain privilege, falling somewhere on a spectrum of willfulness, and thus represents a cognitive failure.[27]The matter is more complicated in the case of deep ignorance, which is a particularly recalcitrant form of ignorance, and which does not, at first glance, appear willful. Peels, for one, has argued that in these cases ignorance is exculpating.[28]But he is not considering motivated cases of ignorance. I would argue that in these cases, there is epistemic culpability even in the absence of willfulness, in so far as the individuals in question benefit from their ignorance.[29]Although there is more to be said on this matter, it should be clear that whether we are talking about disbelieving ignorance, suspending ignorance, or deep ignorance, individuals who lack true beliefs about the crushing impact of racism and misogyny on black people and women are in a privileged position where int hey effectively do not need to know. These individuals are not critically alive to the ways that the epistemic situation has been distorted, as Fricker (2016, 173) has put it, because, I would add, they do not need to be. These individuals have the luxury of being able to move around in the world without experiencing the everyday brutality of systemic racism and misogyny, which is something that individuals with marginalized identities will never have.
I had that thought after watching Barry Jenkins’s stunning 2016 film Moonlight,[30]which tells the story of Chiron, who is poor, black, and gay, and whom we meet at three critical points early on in his life. At each stage we see Chiron’s strength and his vulnerability, often juxtaposed; we see a character being built and broken, and through his story we learn something about the reality of being a gay black man in America. By the time we meet Chiron in act 3,he is in his twenties, having spent his teenage years being bullied before finally fighting back. This Chiron has known the tenderness of romantic touch only once in his life, and he is unrecognizable from his younger self. He has layered his body so that it is no longer a target, constructed his masculinity through muscle and grills so that it has become impenetrable. Yet Jenkins allows the audience to see through the beefed-up body to the person within, and to his humanity. We see this Chiron emerge out of his own artifice in order to reunite with the man who once showed him affection, his vulnerability now becoming his true strength, and a remarkable scene emerges.
The pageantry of Chiron’s masculinity in Moonlight brings to mind an early passage in Ta-Nehisi Coates’s Between the World and Me, in which Coates unmasks the meaning behind the protective layering. In reflecting on the black Baltimore of his youth, Coates says,
It was always right in front of me. The fear was there in the extravagant boys of my neighborhood, in their large rings and medallions, their big puffy coats and full-length fur-collared leathers, which was their armor against their world. …I think back on those boys now and all I see is fear, and all I see is them girding themselves against the ghosts of the bad old days when the Mississippi mob gathered ‘round their grandfathers so that the branches of the black body might be torched, then cut away.(Coates 2015, 14)
Coates’s book is a meditation on a question he poses early on in the narrative, “How do I live free in this black body?” (2015, 12). His story urges us to consider what it is like to be a black man (or, in the case of McCraney and Jenkins’s movie, a gay black man) in America. Engaging imaginatively with these stories of black racialized identities told by black voices helps us to see Chiron’s beefed up body as stemming, at least in part, from deeply rooted intergenerational trauma.
Representation, Empathy,and #MeToo
Marginalized stories thrust evidence of alternative lives into the spotlight, pushing back against dominant but false narratives that are perpetuated by bad epistemic practices, which are cultivated in order to maintain privilege. They enable us to learn something about the world as experienced from social positions other than our own. And perhaps unsurprisingly, the more we know about people, the harder it is to deny their humanity. Empirical studies tell us that exposure to disparate social types can minimize prejudice when certain conditions are met,[31]such that getting to know members of other social types makes it harder to hold negative stereotypes about them.[32]This notion that intergroup contact reduces prejudice is not uncontested, but recent research on the subject is encouraging.[33]A recent study of door-to-door political canvassing, for instance, shows that you do not need intense or prolonged intervention to see change, a 10-minute face-to-face conversation can have an impact on reducing prejudice (Broockman and Kalla 2016; Denizet-Lewis 2016).This phenomenon has been explained by the idea of “affective perspective-taking, “which can be seen as one facet of empathy.[34]Empathy, narrowly defined, is a sensitivity to others with whom we identify, whose feelings we can also feel, in some sense. As such, empathy can result in an implicit preference for in-group members(which is why some argue it should not be used as a basis for morality),[35]but affective perspective-taking can be a powerful way to bring about empathic concern for those not in one’s own social group. As Decety and Cowell (2014b, 526) put it, affective perspective-taking is “a strategy that can be successfully used to reduce group partiality and to expand the circle of empathic concern from the tribe to all humanity.”[36]
We saw an example of this in action not too long ago, in September 2018, in Washington, DC, at the height of the Senate Judiciary Committee hearings for the Brett Kavanaugh Supreme Court nomination, in a highly publicized encounter between Republican Senator Jeff Flake of Arizona and Ana Maria Archila and Maria Gallagher. These women, both sexual assault survivors, demanded, in a brief elevator encounter, that Flake witness their pain and acknowledge the need for perpetrators of sexual violence to take responsibility for their actions. [37]Almost directly following this encounter, Flake, reversing his previous position on the matter, demanded an investigation into the sexual assault allegations that had been brought against Kavanaugh.[38]
In telling their stories of sexual violence and sexual harassment, women have the power to challenge dominant misconceptions, overturn rape myths, and debunk traditional victim-blaming narratives, thereby effecting broad social and cultural change through their testimony. The profusion of #MeToo testimony by a diverse group of women brings to light the range of experiences suffered by survivors of sexual violence and sexual harassment. The long-term consequences of this have yet to be played out, but the immediate result is a positive uptick in epistemic value for the society at large via an increase in truth, knowledge, and understanding.
1.3 The Benefit to Tellers (Uptick #3)
The third area in which #MeToo stories result in a positive increase in epistemic value is with the teller herself. Although in telling herstory of sexual violence or harassment the survivor takes great risks(which I discuss below), if these can be alleviated there is the possibility of tremendous benefits for tellers, at least when their stories are properly heard. The epistemic gains can be significant, and there can also be emotive, therapeutic, and ethical gains for the teller. Having marginalized stories recognized by a receptive audience can help survivors combat the shame and silence that all too often piggybacks on nonnormative life experiences. Telling our stories can be a way of saying, this is not on me, this is not my fault, I have nothing to be ashamed of, and my truth is worth making known. For the teller, giving voice to her story can help give her life meaning, craft her identity, and maximize herself-worth and autonomy. It can be a privilege to tell one’s story.
The opportunity that #MeToo has created for women to speak from a place of lived experience—and in particular women from the marginalized communities, including trans women, genderqueer and gender nonconforming women, women of colour, and women who are disabled(and especially women at the intersection of these communities)—and to do so on their own terms, brings into focus the positive epistemic value which tellers derive from first-person narratives of these sorts. Just imagine the boost for those women whose testimony is not dismissed due to faulty misperceptions of credibility. Imagine that instead of being denied status as a knower, they are recognized as having earned that status.
Part 2:The High Cost of Survivor Stories
2.1 Testimony: Costs and Credibility
And yet, the importance of these stories to hearers, to society at large, and potentially to the teller herself compels us to consider the normative implications of this kind of testimony. On standard philosophical accounts of testimony, a teller’s word is assessed on the basis of two factors: her sincerity and her competence, which combine to determine her overall trustworthiness, or credibility.[43]In the case of first-person testimonials like #MeToo, where individuals are recounting an aspect of their own lives, the question of competence usually takes a back seat to the question of sincerity. That is, the issue is not typically “how did you come to know that?” but rather, “why should we believe you?” This question about the veracity of testimony is a central one in contemporary debates and is typically framed as a question about the hearer, that is, whether the hearer has a presumptive right to believe, absent any positive evidence about the reliability of the teller.[44] But in cases where there is evidence about the reliability of the teller, this question is normatively idle. In these cases, the evidence determines the reliability. So why is it that in standard cases of testimony about sexual violence or sexual harassment, the evidence is presented as split, framed as a “he said/she said ”scenario? It could be because these crimes often occur behind closed doors, which means there is seldom any eye-witness testimony. But we need to ask why eye-witness testimony is privileged in these cases, since if we broaden our gaze, we can see a mountain of other evidence—specifically, the evidence of the high costs of the teller’s testimony. For even if we know no other facts about her, as is often the case in #MeToo testimonials, we know that simply in virtue of telling her story, and thus coming up against the juggernaut of patriarchy, she has placed herself directly in harm’s way. And this fact bears directly on the question of what hearer sought to believe.
2.2 Practical Rationality
The connection between truth-telling and risk-taking is underwritten by the notion of practical rationality. Rationality is one of those philosophical concepts that can be unwieldy, but here I rely on a straightforward meaning of the term that, in practical matters, dictates that individuals actin ways that maximize their goals(Wedgwood 2014).[45]This characterization will suffice to generate a number of inferential moves, for if these tellers aim to survive and prosper, and to be treated with dignity and respect by their social groups, then on pain of rationality they would not give testimony that jeopardizes those goals—not unless they had a very good reason to do so, such as wanting the truth of what happened to them to be heard and believed. To suppose otherwise would be to attribute to this particular class of tellers a kind of cognitive dysfunction typically reserved for individuals who suffer from serious mental illness, drug-induced altered states, or some form of extreme irrationality.
Conclusion
References
Alexander, Michelle.2010. The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of
Colorblindness. New York:New Press.
‘Benefiting From’to ‘Contributing To.’” Philosophy of Education Yearbook,
292–300.
Isle. 2015. Issue Brief: Sexual Violence Against Women in Canada. Ottawa:
Status of Women Canada.
Ecco.
Princeton University Press.
Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Experiment on Door-to-Door Canvassing.” Science352(6282):220–225.
doi:10.1126/science.aad9713.
and Transgender Women and Gender Diverse and Two Spirit People on the
Basis of Sexual Orientation, Gender Identity and Gender Expression.Egale
Canada Human Rights Trust.
doi:10.2307/2185680.
Atria Books.
Press.
and Empathy.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences18 (7): 337–339.doi:10.1016/j
.tics.2014.04.008.
Perspectives on Psychological Science9(5):525–537. doi:10.1177
/1745691614545130.
Conversation.” New York Times Magazine,April 7.
https://www.nytimes.com/2016/04/10/magazine/how-do-you-change-
voters-minds-have-a-conversation.html?_r=0.
as Baseless.” Globe and Mail, February 3.
http://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/investigations/unfounded-sexual-
assault-canada-main/article33891309/.
Hypatia26(2):236–257.doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01177.x.
Jim Crow.” New York University Law Review 87 (1): 101–146.
York: Farrar Straus & Giroux.
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes61:57–83.
in History and Philosophy of Science Part A33 (2):373–383.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance, edited byRik Peels and Martijn Blaauw,
160–177. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trans Experiences.” In The Routledge Companion to Feminist Philosophy,
edited byAnn Garry, Serene J. Khader, and Alison Stone, 268–278.New York:
Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
Domestic Abuse to Political Terror.New York: Basic Books.
Ma’ayan Anafi. 2016. The Report of the 2015 US Transgender Survey.
Washington, DC: National Center for Transgender Equality.
www.transequality.org/sites/default/files/docs/USTS-Full-Report-FINAL.PDF.
Jenkins. A24 Films.
The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance, edited by Rik Peels and Martijn
Blaauw, 12–32. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Allegations of Sexual Assault: An Analysis of Ten Years of Reported Cases.”
Violence Against Women 16 (12):1318–1334.
doi:10.1177/1077801210387747.
Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
Press.
Responses to Sexual Harassment. Center for Employment Equity.
doi:10.2139/ssrn.3407960.
Freedom Magazine,July/August,10–12.
Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations.Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
———.2016. “Ignorance and Racial Insensitivity.”In The Epistemic Dimensions of
Ignorance, edited by Rik Peels and Martijn Blaauw, 178–201.Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 11–38. Albany: State University
of New York Press.
Ogden, Pat, Kekuni Minton, and Clare Pain, 2006.Trauma and the Body: A
Sensorimotor Approach to Psychotherapy, New York: W.W. Norton.
Peels, Rik.2010.“What Is Ignorance?”Philosophia38:57–67.doi:10.1007/s11406-
009-9202-8.
———.2011.“Ignorance Is Lack of True Belief: A Rejoinder to Le Morvan.”
Philosophia 39:345–355.doi:10.1007/s11406-010-9301-6.
———.2012.“The New View on Ignorance Undefeated.”Philosophia40:741–750.
doi:10.1007/s11406-012-9364-7.
———.2014“What Kind of Ignorance Excuses? Two Neglected Issues.” Philosophical
Quarterly 64 (256): 478–496. doi:10.1093/pq/pqu013.
Pettigrew, Thomas, and Linda Tropp.2006. “A Meta-Analytic Test of Intergroup
Contact Theory.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 90 (5):751–
783.doi:10.1037/0022-3514.90.5.751.
Prinz, Jesse. 2011. “Against Empathy.” In “Empathy and Ethics,”edited by Remy
Debes,special issue, Southern Journal of Philosophy 49 (S1): 214–233.
doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.2011.00069.x
Pritchard, Duncan.2007. “Recent Work on Epistemic Value.” American Philosophical
Quarterly 44(2):85–110.’
Social Philosophy1 (1):1–28.
Trauma Treatment. New York: W. W. Norton.
Social Philosophy43(3):256–273.doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.2012.01564.x.
An Experimental Field Test of the Contact Hypothesis.” Psychological Science
19(7):717–723.
magazine, February 10.http://nymag.com/scienceofus/2017/02/the-
contact-hypothesis-offers-hope-for-the-world.html.
Can Do. New York: W.W. Norton.
Cambridge University Press.
Anger. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Effects of Overwhelming Experience on the Mind, Body, and Society, edited
by Bessel A. van der Kolk, Alexander C. McFarlane and Lars Weisaeth, 214–
241.New York: Guilford Press.
———. 2006.Foreword to Trauma and the Body: A Sensorimotor Approach to
Psychotherapy, edited by Pat Ogden, Kekuni Minton, and Claire Pain.New
York: W.W. Norton.
False Beliefs.”American Philosophical Quarterly46(4): 373–386.
–338. doi:10.1111/phib.12055.
Narrative.”Cerebrum, Jan.–Feb. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc
/articles/PMC4445577/.
KARYN L. FREEDMAN is an associate professorof philosophy at the University of Guelph. Her research interests are in epistemology and feminist philosophy. She has published papers on a variety of subjects, including testimony, disagreement, epistemic akrasia, and psychological trauma. Her book, One Hour in Paris: A True Story of Rape and Recovery, won the 2015 British Columbia National Award for Canadian Non-Fiction.
About this reading
This chapter reproduces the article:
Freedman, Karyn L. 2020. “The Epistemic Significance of #MeToo.” Feminist Philosophy Quarterly 6 (2). https://doi.org/10.5206/fpq/2020.2.8030.This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License (CC BY 4.0). It is reprinted here without modification.